Vagueness
Vagueness of
meaning was a concern in analytic language philosophy long before it referred to the fuzzy boundaries of material objects that led to
Peter Unger's "Problem of the Many."
Unger's vagueness comes from the lack of any precise boundary for a cloud in the sky,
as science seems clearly to say, our clouds are almost wholly
composed of tiny water droplets, and the dispersion of these droplets, in
the sky or the atmosphere, is always, in fact, a gradual matter. With
pretty much any route out of even a comparatively clean cloud’s center,
there is no stark stopping place to be encountered. Rather, anywhere
near anything presumed a boundary, there’s only a gradual decrease in
the density of droplets fit, more or less, to be constituents of a cloud
that’s there.
The
quantifiable information in any physical object far exceeds the amount that is picked out by human perceptions or conceptions of what the object
is. A similar problem exists for an ideal or fictional object, especially as represented in human language, because of the fecundity of the human mind to imagine variations in meaning.
In our quest to understand the fundamental nature of reality, our understanding of quantum physics shows that the most microscopic objects have an irreducible vagueness in the form of
Heisenberg's
uncertainty principle. The
wave function is a probabilistic estimate of the
possible locations for finding a particle. The possible locations are virtually infinite compared to the particle size. We might say that quantum objects have the highest degree of metaphysical vagueness known.
In his 1975 article, "Vagueness, Truth, and Logic," Kit Fine gave specific examples of different types of vagueness in analytic language philosophy:
Suppose that the meaning of the natural number predicates,
nice1, nice2, and nice3, is given by the following clauses:
(1) (a) n is nice1 if n > 15
(b) n is not nice1 if n < 13
(2) (a) n is nice2 if and only if n > 15
(b) n is nice2 if and only if n > 14
(3) n is nice3 if and only if n > 15
Clause (1) is reminiscent of Carnap's (1952) meaning postulates. Clauses
(2) (a)-(b) are not intended to be equivalent to a single contradictory
clause; somehow the separate clauses should be insulated from one an
other. Then nice1 is vague, its meaning is under-determined; nice2 is
ambiguous, its meaning is over-determined; and nice3 is highly general
or un-specific. The sentence 'there are infinitely many nice3 twin primes'
possibly undecidable but certainly not vague or ambiguous.
("Vagueness, Truth, and Logic," Synthese, Vol. 30, No. 3/4, On the Logic Semantics of Vagueness (Apr. - May, 1975),
In the 1980 third edition of his
Reference and Generality, Peter Geach, asked how many hairs of a cat are essential to its
identity
Vagueness and the Two-Slit Experiment
We can define vagueness precisely as the volume of space around a particle trajectory where the square of the quantum wave function (we call this the "possibilities function") has a significant non-zero value. This is the volume where there is some probability of finding the particle.
When that vague probability spreads out so as to hit both slits, the famous interference pattern appears on the distant screen. If the non-zero probability, the vagueness, is narrowed or focussed to fall onto just one of the two slits, the interference pattern disappears. It is the information in the abstract probability that interferes with itself in the
two-slit experiment.
References
Lewis, D. (1993). Many, but almost one.
Ontology, causality and mind, 23-42.
Chicago
Lowe, E. J. (1982).
The paradox of the 1,001 cats.
Analysis, 42(1), 27-30.
Chicago
Lowe, E. J. (1982).
On being a cat.
Analysis, 42(3), 174-177.
Lowe, E. J. (1995).
The Problem of the Many and the Vagueness of Constitution.
Analysis, 55(3), 179-182.
For Teachers
To hide this material, click on the Normal link.
For Scholars
To hide this material, click on the Teacher or Normal link.
Scholar
Normal |
Teacher |
Scholar