Philosophers
Mortimer Adler Rogers Albritton Alexander of Aphrodisias Samuel Alexander William Alston Anaximander G.E.M.Anscombe Anselm Louise Antony Thomas Aquinas Aristotle David Armstrong Harald Atmanspacher Robert Audi Augustine J.L.Austin A.J.Ayer Alexander Bain Mark Balaguer Jeffrey Barrett William Barrett William Belsham Henri Bergson George Berkeley Isaiah Berlin Richard J. Bernstein Bernard Berofsky Robert Bishop Max Black Susanne Bobzien Emil du Bois-Reymond Hilary Bok Laurence BonJour George Boole Émile Boutroux F.H.Bradley C.D.Broad Michael Burke Lawrence Cahoone C.A.Campbell Joseph Keim Campbell Rudolf Carnap Carneades Nancy Cartwright Gregg Caruso Ernst Cassirer David Chalmers Roderick Chisholm Chrysippus Cicero Randolph Clarke Samuel Clarke Anthony Collins Antonella Corradini Diodorus Cronus Jonathan Dancy Donald Davidson Mario De Caro Democritus Daniel Dennett Jacques Derrida René Descartes Richard Double Fred Dretske John Dupré John Earman Laura Waddell Ekstrom Epictetus Epicurus Herbert Feigl Arthur Fine John Martin Fischer Frederic Fitch Owen Flanagan Luciano Floridi Philippa Foot Alfred Fouilleé Harry Frankfurt Richard L. Franklin Bas van Fraassen Michael Frede Gottlob Frege Peter Geach Edmund Gettier Carl Ginet Alvin Goldman Gorgias Nicholas St. John Green H.Paul Grice Ian Hacking Ishtiyaque Haji Stuart Hampshire W.F.R.Hardie Sam Harris William Hasker R.M.Hare Georg W.F. Hegel Martin Heidegger Heraclitus R.E.Hobart Thomas Hobbes David Hodgson Shadsworth Hodgson Baron d'Holbach Ted Honderich Pamela Huby David Hume Ferenc Huoranszki Frank Jackson William James Lord Kames Robert Kane Immanuel Kant Tomis Kapitan Walter Kaufmann Jaegwon Kim William King Hilary Kornblith Christine Korsgaard Saul Kripke Thomas Kuhn Andrea Lavazza Christoph Lehner Keith Lehrer Gottfried Leibniz Jules Lequyer Leucippus Michael Levin Joseph Levine George Henry Lewes C.I.Lewis David Lewis Peter Lipton C. Lloyd Morgan John Locke Michael Lockwood E. Jonathan Lowe John R. Lucas Lucretius Alasdair MacIntyre Ruth Barcan Marcus James Martineau Storrs McCall Hugh McCann Colin McGinn Michael McKenna Brian McLaughlin John McTaggart Paul E. Meehl Uwe Meixner Alfred Mele Trenton Merricks John Stuart Mill Dickinson Miller G.E.Moore Thomas Nagel Otto Neurath Friedrich Nietzsche John Norton P.H.Nowell-Smith Robert Nozick William of Ockham Timothy O'Connor Parmenides David F. Pears Charles Sanders Peirce Derk Pereboom Steven Pinker Plato Karl Popper Porphyry Huw Price H.A.Prichard Protagoras Hilary Putnam Willard van Orman Quine Frank Ramsey Ayn Rand Michael Rea Thomas Reid Charles Renouvier Nicholas Rescher C.W.Rietdijk Richard Rorty Josiah Royce Bertrand Russell Paul Russell Gilbert Ryle Jean-Paul Sartre Kenneth Sayre T.M.Scanlon Moritz Schlick Arthur Schopenhauer John Searle Wilfrid Sellars Alan Sidelle Ted Sider Henry Sidgwick Walter Sinnott-Armstrong J.J.C.Smart Saul Smilansky Michael Smith Baruch Spinoza L. Susan Stebbing Isabelle Stengers George F. Stout Galen Strawson Peter Strawson Eleonore Stump Francisco Suárez Richard Taylor Kevin Timpe Mark Twain Peter Unger Peter van Inwagen Manuel Vargas John Venn Kadri Vihvelin Voltaire G.H. von Wright David Foster Wallace R. Jay Wallace W.G.Ward Ted Warfield Roy Weatherford C.F. von Weizsäcker William Whewell Alfred North Whitehead David Widerker David Wiggins Bernard Williams Timothy Williamson Ludwig Wittgenstein Susan Wolf Scientists David Albert Michael Arbib Walter Baade Bernard Baars Jeffrey Bada Leslie Ballentine Gregory Bateson John S. Bell Mara Beller Charles Bennett Ludwig von Bertalanffy Susan Blackmore Margaret Boden David Bohm Niels Bohr Ludwig Boltzmann Emile Borel Max Born Satyendra Nath Bose Walther Bothe Jean Bricmont Hans Briegel Leon Brillouin Stephen Brush Henry Thomas Buckle S. H. Burbury Melvin Calvin Donald Campbell Sadi Carnot Anthony Cashmore Eric Chaisson Gregory Chaitin Jean-Pierre Changeux Rudolf Clausius Arthur Holly Compton John Conway Jerry Coyne John Cramer Francis Crick E. P. Culverwell Antonio Damasio Olivier Darrigol Charles Darwin Richard Dawkins Terrence Deacon Lüder Deecke Richard Dedekind Louis de Broglie Stanislas Dehaene Max Delbrück Abraham de Moivre Paul Dirac Hans Driesch John Eccles Arthur Stanley Eddington Gerald Edelman Paul Ehrenfest Manfred Eigen Albert Einstein George F. R. Ellis Hugh Everett, III Franz Exner Richard Feynman R. A. Fisher David Foster Joseph Fourier Philipp Frank Steven Frautschi Edward Fredkin Lila Gatlin Michael Gazzaniga Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen GianCarlo Ghirardi J. Willard Gibbs Nicolas Gisin Paul Glimcher Thomas Gold A. O. Gomes Brian Goodwin Joshua Greene Dirk ter Haar Jacques Hadamard Mark Hadley Patrick Haggard J. B. S. Haldane Stuart Hameroff Augustin Hamon Sam Harris Ralph Hartley Hyman Hartman John-Dylan Haynes Donald Hebb Martin Heisenberg Werner Heisenberg John Herschel Basil Hiley Art Hobson Jesper Hoffmeyer Don Howard William Stanley Jevons Roman Jakobson E. T. Jaynes Pascual Jordan Ruth E. Kastner Stuart Kauffman Martin J. Klein William R. Klemm Christof Koch Simon Kochen Hans Kornhuber Stephen Kosslyn Daniel Koshland Ladislav Kovàč Leopold Kronecker Rolf Landauer Alfred Landé Pierre-Simon Laplace David Layzer Joseph LeDoux Gilbert Lewis Benjamin Libet David Lindley Seth Lloyd Hendrik Lorentz Josef Loschmidt Ernst Mach Donald MacKay Henry Margenau Owen Maroney Humberto Maturana James Clerk Maxwell Ernst Mayr John McCarthy Warren McCulloch N. David Mermin George Miller Stanley Miller Ulrich Mohrhoff Jacques Monod Emmy Noether Alexander Oparin Abraham Pais Howard Pattee Wolfgang Pauli Massimo Pauri Roger Penrose Steven Pinker Colin Pittendrigh Max Planck Susan Pockett Henri Poincaré Daniel Pollen Ilya Prigogine Hans Primas Henry Quastler Adolphe Quételet Lord Rayleigh Jürgen Renn Juan Roederer Jerome Rothstein David Ruelle Tilman Sauer Jürgen Schmidhuber Erwin Schrödinger Aaron Schurger Sebastian Seung Thomas Sebeok Claude Shannon David Shiang Abner Shimony Herbert Simon Dean Keith Simonton B. F. Skinner Lee Smolin Ray Solomonoff Roger Sperry John Stachel Henry Stapp Tom Stonier Antoine Suarez Leo Szilard Max Tegmark Libb Thims William Thomson (Kelvin) Giulio Tononi Peter Tse Francisco Varela Vlatko Vedral Mikhail Volkenstein Heinz von Foerster Richard von Mises John von Neumann Jakob von Uexküll John B. Watson Daniel Wegner Steven Weinberg Paul A. Weiss Herman Weyl John Wheeler Wilhelm Wien Norbert Wiener Eugene Wigner E. O. Wilson Stephen Wolfram H. Dieter Zeh Ernst Zermelo Wojciech Zurek Konrad Zuse Fritz Zwicky |
Composition (Parts and Wholes)
Debates about the relation of parts to wholes is a major part of modern metaphysics. Many puzzles have to do with different persistence conditions of the "parts" of a composited whole.
Mereological universalism or extensional mereology is an abstract idea, defined in 1937 by Stanislaw Leśniewski and later by Henry Leonard and Nelson Goodman (1940). It claims that any collection of things, for example the members of a set in symbolic logic, can be considered as the parts of a whole, a "fusion" or "mereological sum," and thus can compose an object. Critics of this idea says that such arbitrary collections are just "scattered objects." A mind-independent connection between objects is needed for them to be integral "parts."
Mereological essentialism is Roderick Chisholm's radical idea that every whole has its parts necessarily and in every possible world. This goes too far. No physical object can maintain its parts indefinitely and freeze its identity over time. Our third axiom of identity is
Id3. Everything is identical to itself in all respects at each instant of time, but different in some respects from itself at any other time.Mereological nihilists, such as Peter van Inwagen and the early Peter Unger denied the existence of composites, seeing them as simples (partless entities) arranged to look like a composite object. For him, a table is "simples arranged table-wise." Van Inwagen made an exception for living objects. Surprisingly, he based the composite nature of biological entities on the Cartesian dualist view that humans are thinking beings. Van Inwagen then could see no obvious demarcation level at which even the simplest living things should not be treated as composite objects. Information philosophy and metaphysics ask who or what is doing the arranging? Information provides a more fundamental reason than van Inwagen's for treating living things as integrated composites and not simply mereological sums of scattered objects. Furthermore, it extends a true composite nature to artifacts and to groupings of living things because they share a teleonomic property – a purpose. And it shows how some "proper parts" of these composites can have a holistic relation with their own parts, enforcing transitivity of part/whole relations. A process that makes a composite object an integrated whole we call teleonomic (following Colin Pittendrigh, Jacques Monod, and Ernst Mayr) to distinguish it from a teleological cause with a "telos" pre-existing all life. We will show that teleonomy is the explanatory force behind van Inwagen's "arrangement" of simple parts. Biological parts, which we can call biomers, are communicating systems that share information via biological messaging with other parts of their wholes, and in many cases communicate with other living and non-living parts of their environments. These communications function to maintain the biological integrity (or identity) of the organism and they control its growth. Artifacts have their teleonomy imposed by their creators. Biocommunications are messages transferring information, for example inside the simplest single-cell organisms. For the first few billion years of life these were the only living things, and they still dominate our planet. Their messages are the direct ancestors of messages between cells in multicellular organisms. And they have evolved to become all human communications, including the puzzles and problems of metaphysics. A straight line of evolution goes from the first biological message to this Metaphysicist web page. Like many metaphysical problems, composition arose in the quarrels between Stoics and Academic skeptics that generated several ancient puzzles still debated today. But it has roots in Aristotle's definition of the essence (ουσία), the unchanging "Being" of an object. We will show that Aristotle's essentialism has a biological basis that is best understood today as a biomereological essentialism. It goes beyond mereological sums of scattered objects because of the teleonomy shared between the parts, whether living or dead, of a biomeric whole. First, back to Aristotle, Is Aristotle here the source of the four Stoic genera or categories?
The term “substance” (οὐσία) is used, if not in more, at least in four principal cases; for both the essence (εἶναι), and the universal (καθόλου) and the genus (γένος) are held to be the substance of the particular (ἑκάστου), and fourthly the substrate (ὑποκείμενον). The substrate is that of which the rest are predicated, while it is not itself predicated of anything else. Hence we must first determine its nature, for the primary substrate (ὑποκείμενον) is considered to be in the truest sense substance.The essence of an object, the "kind" or "sort" of object that it "is", its "constitution," its "identity," includes those "proper" parts of the object without which it would cease to be that sort or kind. Without a single essential part, it loses its absolute identity. While this is strictly "true," for all practical purposes most objects retain the overwhelming fraction of the information that describes them from moment to moment, so that information philosophy offers a new and quantitative measure of "sameness" to traditional philosophy, a measure that is difficult or impossible to describe in ordinary language. Nevertheless, since even the smallest change in time does make an entity at t + Δt different from what it was at t, this has given rise to the idea of "temporal parts."
Temporal Parts
Philosophers and theologians have for many years argued for distinct temporal parts, with the idea that each new part is a completely new creation ex nihilo. Even modern physicists (e.g., Hugh Everett III) talk as if parallel universes are brought into existence at an instant by quantum experiments that collapse the wave function.
David Lewis, who claims there are many possible worlds, is a proponent of many temporal parts. His theory of "perdurance" asserts that the persistence through time of an object is as a series of completely distinct entities, one for every instant of time. Lewis's work implies that the entire infinite number of his possible worlds (as "real" and actual as our world, he claims), must also be entirely created anew at every instant.
While this makes for great science fiction and popularizes metaphysics, at some point attempts to understand the fundamental nature of reality must employ Occam's Razor and recognize the fundamental conservation laws of physics. If a new temporal part is created ab initio, why should it bear any resemblance at all to its earlier version?
It is extravagant in the extreme to suggest that all matter disappears and reappears at every instant of time. It is astonishing enough that matter can spontaneously be converted into energy and back again at a later time.
Most simple things (the elementary particles, the atoms and molecules of ordinary matter, etc.) are in stable states that exist continuously for long periods of time, and these compose larger objects that persist through "endurance," as Lewis describes the alternative to his "perdurance." Large objects are not absolutely identical to themselves at earlier instants of time, but the differences are infinitesimal in information content.
The doctrine of temporal parts ignores the physical connections between all the "simples" at one instant and at the following moment. It is as if this is an enormous version of the Zeno paradox of the arrow. The arrow cannot possibly be moving when examined at an instant. The basic laws of physics describe the continuous motions of every particle. They generally show very slow changes in configuration – the organizational arrangement of the particles that constitutes abstract information about an object.
One might charitably interpret Lewis as admitting the endurance of the elementary particles (or whatever partless simples he might accept) and that perdurance is only describing the constant change in configuration, the arrangement of the simples that constitute or compose the whole.
Then Lewis's temporal parts would be a series of self-identical objects that are not absolutely identical to their predecessors and successors, just a temporal series of highly theoretical abstract ideas, perhaps at the same level of (absurd) abstraction as his possible worlds?.
Mereology
Mereology is the study of parts which compose a whole. What exactly is a part? And what constitutes a whole? For each concept, there is a strict philosophical sense, an ordinary sense, and a functional or teleonomic sense.
In the strict sense, a part is just some subset of the whole. The whole itself is sometimes called an "improper part."
In the ordinary sense, a part is distinguishable, in principle separable, from other neighboring parts of some whole. The smallest possible parts are those that have no smaller parts. In physics, these are the atoms, or today the elementary particles, of matter.
In the functional sense, we can say that a part serves some purpose in the whole. This means that it has may be considered a whole in its own right, subordinate to any purpose of the whole entity. Teleonomic examples are the pedals or wheel of a bicycle, the organs of an animal body, or the organelles in a cell.
The same three-part analysis applies to the question of what composes a "whole" object.
Some philosophers (e.g., Peter Unger and Peter van Inwagen) deny that composite objects exist. This is called "mereological nihiism," though a more accurate name would be "holistic nihilism," since it is composite wholes that they deny. They do not deny the parts, which they call "simples." Van Inwagen argues, for example, that tables are just "simples arranged tablewise," where the simples are partless objects.
Note that the arrangement of parts is not material, but immaterial information.
The strict philosophical definition of a composite whole, especially in analytic language philosophy, is just its being picked out by a philosopher for analysis. An example might be "there is a table," or in Quine's existential quantification form, "∃ x (x = 'a table')."
The ordinary sense of a whole is an object that is distinguishable from its neighboring objects. But such a whole may be just a part of some larger whole, up to the universe.
The teleonomic sense of an object is that it seems to have a purpose, the Greeks called it a telos, either intrinsic as in all living things, or extrinsic as in all artifacts, where the purpose was invented by the object's creator.
The most important example of a teleonomic process is of course biology. Every biological organism starts with a first cell that contains all the information needed to accomplish its "purpose," to grow into a fully developed individual, and, for some, to procreate others of its kind.
By contrast, when a philosopher picks out an arbitrary part of something, declaring it to be a whole something for philosophical purposes, perhaps naming it, the teleonomy is simply the philosopher's intention to analyze it further.
For example, something that has no natural or artifactual basis, that does not "carve nature at the joints," as Plato described it, that arbitrarily and violently divides the otherwise indivisible, is a perfectly valid "idea," an abstract entity. This notion that anything goes for the philosopher to select as a composite whole is known as "mereological universalism."
The combination of arbitrary objects is called a "mereological sum." A frequent example is a combination of the Statue of Liberty and the Eiffel Tower, although there is a strong teleonomic component to this mereological sum as they are part of the oeuvre of the great designer and engineer Alexandre-Gustave Eiffel. Remember, everything is identical to anything else "in some respect."
Mereological Essentialism
Aristotle knew that most living things can survive the loss of various parts (limbs, for example), but not others (the head). By analogy, he thought that other objects (and even concepts) could have parts (or properties) that are essential to its definition and other properties or qualities that are merely accidental.
Mereological essentialism is the study of those essential parts.
At his presidential address to the twenty-fourth annual
meeting of the Metaphysical Society of America in 1973, Rod Chisholm defined "mereological essentialism," the idea that if some object has parts, then those parts are essential, metaphysically necessary, to the particular object..
I shall consider a philosophical puzzle pertaining to the concepts of whole and part. The proper solution, I believe, will throw light upon some of the most important questions of metaphysics. The puzzle pertains to what I shall call the principle of mereological essentialism. The principle may be formulated by saying that, for any whole x, if x has y as one of its parts then y is part of x in every possible world in which x exists. The principle may also be put by saying that every whole has the parts that it has necessarily, or by saying that if y is part of x then the property of having y as one of its parts is essential to x. If the principle is true, then if y is ever part of x, y will be part of x as long as x exists.Chisholm draws three important conclusions. (Al) If x is a part of y and y is a part of z, then x is a part of z (this is the transitivity of parthood). (A2) If x is a part of y, then y is not a part of x (the whole is an improper part of itself). (A3) If x is a part of y, then y is such that in every possible world in which y exists x is a part of y (can we explain this?).For Aristotle, and in ordinary use, not every part of a whole is a necessary part (let alone in all possible worlds). How does Chisholm defend such an extreme view as his A3? We can speculate that he assumes that the essential nature of something must preserve its identity, so that A3 can be rewritten (A3') If x is a part of y, then y is an essential, that is a necessary, part of y needed to maintain its identity.Much of the verbal quibbling in metaphysical disputes is about objects that are defined by language conventions as opposed to objects that are "natural kinds". Mereological universalism is the idea that an arbitrary collection of objects or parts of objects can be considered a conceptual whole – a "mereological sum" – for some purpose or other (mostly to provoke an empty debate with other metaphysicians). Modern metaphysics examines the relations of parts to whole, whole to parts, and parts to parts within a whole using the abstract axioms of set theory, a vital part of analytic language philosophy today. Because a set can be made up of any list of things, whether they have any physical integrity or even any conceivable connections, other than their membership in the arbitrary set. Consider the "whole" made up of the Eiffel Tower and the Statue of Liberty! Mereology is a venerable subject. The Greeks worried about part/whole questions, usually in the context of the persistence of an object when a part is removed and the question of an object's identity. Is the Ship of Theseus the same ship when some of the planks have been replaced? Does Dion survive the removal of his foot?
“When I use a word,” Humpty Dumpty said, in rather a scornful tone, “it means just what I choose it to mean—neither more nor less."
The idea that an arbitrary collection of things, a "mereological sum," can be considered a whole, does violence to our common sense notion of a whole object. It is an extreme example of the arbitrary connection between words and objects that is the bane of analytic language philosophy.
Mereological universalism also leads to the idea that there are many ways to compose a complex material whole out of a vague collection of simple objects. This is what Peter Unger called the Problem of the Many.
It led Peter van Inwagen to his position of mereological nihilism, that there are no composite wholes. Van Inwagen says there are no tables, only simples arranged table-wise. The "arrangement" is the information in the table. When we can identify the origin of that information, we have the deep metaphysical reason for it essence. Aristotle called the arrangement "the scheme of the ideas."
By matter I mean, for instance, bronze; by shape, the arrangement of the form (τὸ σχῆμα τῆς ἰδέας); and by the combination of the two, the concrete thing: the statue (ἀνδριάς)Van Inwagen makes an exception of living things, and Unger has abandoned his own form of nihilism in recent years. Both Unger and van Inwagen, now accept the idea that they exist. Van Inwagen's says that his argument for living beings as composite objects is based on the Cartesian "cogito," I think, therefore I am. He proposes, (∃y the xs compose y) if and only if
Biomereological Essentialism
Information philosophy provides a much deeper reason for biological organisms as having "proper parts." These biomeric parts are created and maintained by anti-entropic processes that distribute matter and energy to all the vital parts using a biological messaging system to control the distribution of biological materials and free energy. There is a "telos" (or Aristotelian "entelechy," loosely translated as "having the final cause within") implemented by messaging between all the vital parts. We call this teleonomy.
But teleonomy, which depends on the communication of abstract messages between the biomers, is not possible in a materialist metaphysics that denies the existence of immaterial ideas.
We should distinguish ordinary biomeric parts that can fail and be replaced from those that cannot be replaced. These vital biomers are essential in a stronger sense. Without them, the teleonomy of the whole is destroyed. The organism decays to smaller living things and possibly all the way to dead material ("dust to dust").
Basics of Mereology
Why is mereological thinking so important in metaphysics today? With the emphasis on materialism, the material elements appear to be the fundamental parts of reality. A number of thinkers have produced a rich set of papers and books (see Varzi). We can use examples from Achille Varzi's excellent article on mereology in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy that show how we talk about what are parts and wholes. The ways in which parts interact and indeed communicate with one another is not yet a part of today's mereology.
A preliminary caveat is in order. It concerns the very notion of ‘part’ that mereology is about, which does not have an exact counterpart in ordinary language. Broadly speaking, in English we can use ‘part’ to indicate any portion of a given entity. The portion may itself be attached to the remainder, as in (1), or detached, as in (2); it may be cognitively or functionally salient, as in (1)–(2), or arbitrarily demarcated, as in (3); self-connected, as in (1)–(3), or disconnected, as in (4); homogeneous or otherwise well-matched, as in (1)–(4), or gerrymandered, as in (5); material, as in (1)–(5), or immaterial, as in (6); extended, as in (1)–(6), or unextended, as in (7); spatial, as in (1)–(7), or temporal, as in (8); and so on.Note that all of Varzi's examples are conventional (and thus arbitrary ) definitions. So information philosophy could add a few more examples, which might be "natural kinds." Broadly speaking, these are wholes whose parts are demarcated by identifiable natural processes rather than human conventions.(1) The handle is part of the mug.All of these uses illustrate the general notion of ‘part’ that forms the focus of mereology, regardless of any internal distinctions. On the other hand, the English word ‘part’ is sometimes used in a broader sense, too, for instance to designate the relation of material constitution, as in (9), or the relation of mixture composition, as in (10), or the relation of group membership, as in (11): To be sure, many of these "wholes" can survive the loss of some parts. But we are back quibbling. When their efficient/material causes and their formal and final causes are "teleonomic" and not simply arbitrary human conventions, we can say these are "natural kinds." The problem of composition becomes more severe when some metaphysicians consider matter to be infinitely divisible, just as the real number line contains an infinite number of numbers between any two numbers (and a higher order of infinity of irrational numbers!). By contrast, the metaphysicist's view is that matter is discrete, not infinitely divisible like the continuous spatial and temporal dimensions. The Greek materialists argued for simple atoms separated by a void. Ludwig Boltzmann and Albert Einstein showed that the atoms of 19th-century chemistry really exist. In modern physics the simplest elementary particles are quarks, leptons, and bosons. So let's suppose that we have a region of space with two oxygen atoms in it. It seems reasonable to say that it contains two simple things (the atoms).
Peter van Inwagen denies the mereological sum. David Lewis defends it.
Recent mereological debates in metaphysics have taken this form:
Mereological nihilist: There are two things in this region.Now a metaphysicist can still argue cleverly and cogently about the proper number of parts and the choice of the proper whole. The oxygen atoms each contain eight protons, eight neutrons, and eight electrons. So one possible count is the 48 sub-atomic particles that are visible. We can go deeper by noting that the nuclear particles are each made up of three quarks, which are not observable. We then can count 112 parts to the whole? And the metaphysicist has a strong argument for the two simple atoms to be considered a whole. If the two atoms are very close, they can form an oxygen molecule. Even when disassociated, quantum mechanics that treats them as a quasi-molecule is more accurate than a description as two independent atoms. To summarize, the Eiffel Tower and the Statue of Liberty in our arbitrary set do not "compose" a "natural" object just because we group them together in a set.
Van Inwagen and Unger Verbal Dispute
Let's take Peter van Inwagen's version of Peter Unger's 1980 argument for nihilism, which van Inwagen cleverly shows is actually an argument for universalism!
Unger's argument may be compactly formulated as a reductio. Assume I exist. Then certain simples compose_me. Call them 'M'. Now, a single simple is a negligible item indeed. Let y be one of these negligible parts of me—one that is somewhere in my right arm, say. Now, consider the simples that compose me other than y ('M — y'). Since y is so very negligible, M — y could compose a human being just as well as M could. We may say that M and M — y are "equally well suited" to compose human beings. And, of course, for any simple y, "M — y" will be as well suited to compose a human being as M are. Moreover, it would be surprising indeed if there were not a simple z such that "M + z" were as well suited to compose a human being as M are. It would, in fact (if I may once more use this phrase), be intolerably arbitrary to say that M composed a human being although M — y didn't and M — y didn't and M + z didn't. Suppose, therefore, that M — y et al. do compose human beings. Then there are present, in pretty much the same place, the "M — y man," the "M — y man," and the "M + z man." And, of course, simples being so numerous, in any situation in which we should ordinarily say that I was alone in a room, there will be present in that room an enormous, albeit finite, number of men. Some of these will be practically indistinguishable from me and some will be noticeably smaller. There will, for example, be legions of men who are composed entirely of simples that are among the simples we have already mentioned but who lack a right arm. It is, however, perfectly ridiculous to suppose that there are that many men about. But the only alternative is to say that neither M nor any other simples compose a man, and, therefore, to say that I do not exist. Suppose, however, that someone replies by saying that it's even more ridiculous to say that there are no men at all, and that we must therefore suppose that there are many more men than we thought.
References
Burke, M. B. (1994). "Dion and Theon: An essentialist solution to an ancient puzzle." The Journal of Philosophy, 91(3), 129-139.Chisholm, R. M. (1973). "Parts as essential to their wholes." Review of Metaphysics 26: 581-603. Leonard, H. S., & Goodman, N. (1940). "The calculus of individuals and its uses." The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 5(2), 45-55. Lowe, E. J. (1995). "Coinciding objects: in defence of the 'standard account'." Analysis, 55(3), 171-178. Unger, Peter, "The Problem of the Many", Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5.1 (1980): 411-468. Unger, Peter, "The Mental Problems of the Many", Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Vol.1 (2004): 195. Van Inwagen, Peter, 1990, Material Beings, Cornell Van Inwagen, P. (1981). "The Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 62, 123-137. Van Inwagen, Peter. 1987. "When Are Objects Parts?" In Philosophical Perspectives. Vol. 1 Varzi, Achille, Mereology,Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Normal | Teacher | Scholar |